One of the algebraic shortcomings of the natural numbers is that non-zero naturals have no inverses. We can fix this by using the integers. In fact, we can construct the integers using the natural numbers. We do this now and explore some of their properties. But first, we need to introduce some new mathematical ideas to make the construction work.

Definition Equivalence Relations

An equivalence relation \sim over a set XX is a subset of X×XX \times X such that:

  • it is reflexive: (x,x)(x, x) \in \sim for all xXx \in X
  • it is transitive: if (x,y)(x, y) \in \sim and (y,z)(y, z) \in \sim, then (x,z)(x, z) \in \sim
  • it is symmetric: if (x,y)(x, y) \in \sim, then (y,x)(y, x) \in \sim

We often write xyx \sim y instead of (x,y)(x, y) \in \sim. The properties of equivalence relations are inspired from the corresponding properties of equality, ==.

Definition Equivalence Classes

Given an equivalence relation \sim over a set XX and xXx \in X, the set [x]={ξX: ξx}[x] = \{\xi \in X:\ \xi \sim x\} is called the equivalence class of xx. Note that [x][x] is necessarily a subset of XX. Also, by reflexivity, [x][x] is never empty because at least x[x]x \in [x].

Lemma CharEquiClass

Characterization of Equivalence Classes: Given an equivalence relation \sim on a set XX, the following are equivalent:

  • xyx \sim y
  • [x]=[y][x] = [y]
  • [x][y][x] \cap [y] \neq \emptyset

Proof: Suppose xyx \sim y. Now consider an arbitrary element ξ[x]\xi \in [x]. Then, by definition, ξx\xi \sim x. So using transitivity on this and our initial supposition, we get ξy\xi \sim y. Hence, ξ[y]\xi \in [y]. Thus, since ξ\xi was an arbitrary element of [x][x], [x][y][x] \subseteq [y]. By an entirely analogous argument applied to yxy \sim x (which we get from the symmetry of xyx \sim y), we get [y][x][y] \subseteq [x].

Now suppose [x]=[y][x] = [y]. Note that by reflexivity, x[x]x \in [x]. Hence, since [x]=[y][x] = [y], x[y]x \in [y] also. So obviously x[x][y]x \in [x] \cap [y] and we see that [x][y][x] \cap [y] \neq \emptyset.

The readers can show the final implication that if [x][y][x] \cap [y] \neq \emptyset, then xyx \sim y.

Definition Equivalence Quotient

Given an equivalence relation \sim over a set XX, the set of all equivalence classes of elements of XX: X/ ={[x]:xX}X / \sim \ = \{[x]: x \in X\} is called the quotient set relative to \sim. Note that since each [x]X[x] \subseteq X, the quotient set is a subset of the power set PX\mathcal{P}X of XX.

Definition Equivalence Well-Defined-ness

Given a function f:XYf:X \to Y and an equivalence relation \sim on XX, we say that ff is well-defined relative to \sim if whenever xχx \sim \chi we also have f(x)=f(χ)f(x) = f(\chi) for all x,χXx,\chi \in X.

If ff is well-defined relative to \sim, then, there is a natural way to define a function [f][f] from X/X / \sim to YY: simply put [f]([x])=f(x)[f]([x]) = f(x). This is well-defined as a function because if [x]=[χ][x] = [\chi], then by the lemma above, xχx \sim \chi. Hence, the well-defined-ness of ff relative to \sim gives [f](x)=f(x)=f(χ)=[f]([χ]) [f](x) = f(x) = f(\chi) = [f]([\chi]) Thus, [f][f] maps values in its domain to unique values in its codomain, as a function should.

Now we have enough theoretical tools to formally define the integers in terms of the natural numbers

Definition Integers

Consider the set N×N\mathbb{N} \times \mathbb{N}. Now define a relation on this set thus: (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l',r') iff l+r=l+rl + r' = l' + r. This is an equivalence relation:

  • (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l,r) because obviously, l+r=l+rl + r = l + r (addition being a function, l+rl + r represents a unique value).
  • (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l',r') implies (l,r)Z(l,r)(l',r') \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l,r) because l+r=l+rl + r' = l' + r trivially implies l+r=l+rl' + r = l + r'.
  • (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l',r') and (l,r)Z(l,r)(l',r') \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l'',r'') implies (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l'',r''). Showing this is a bit more involved. Well, suppose (a) l+r=l+rl + r' = l' + r and (b) l+r=l+rl' + r'' = l'' + r'. Now, l+(l+r)=(l+r)+l by associativity and commutativity=(l+r)+l by (a)=l+(l+r) by associativity and commutativity \begin{aligned} l + (l'' + r') &= (l + r') + l'' \ \text{by associativity and commutativity}\\ &= (l' + r) + l'' \ \text{by (a)}\\ &= l' + (l'' + r) \ \text{by associativity and commutativity} \end{aligned} At the same time, l+(l+r)=l+(l+r) by (b)=l+(l+r) by associativity and commutativity \begin{aligned} l + (l'' + r') &= l + (l' + r'') \ \text{by (b)}\\ &= l' + (l + r'') \ \text{by associativity and commutativity}\\ \end{aligned} Hence, l+(l+r)=l+(l+r)l' + (l + r'') = l' + (l'' + r) and we can cancel ll' on both sides to get l+r=l+rl + r'' = l'' + r i.e. (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l'',r'') as desired.

To get an intuitive idea of what our equivalence means, pretend for a moment that subtraction over naturals is defined. Then, (l,r)Z(l,r)(l,r) \approx_\mathbb{Z} (l',r') can be translated as lr=lrl - r = l' - r'. But, of course, subtraction is not defined over all pairs of naturals. This is why we write the intuitive translation lr=lrl - r = l' - r' by rearranging the terms as l+r=l+rl + r' = l' + r.

Finally, we define the integers as the quotient set relative to the equivalence above: Z=(N×N)/Z\mathbb{Z} = (\mathbb{N} \times \mathbb{N}) / \approx_\mathbb{Z}.

results matching ""

    No results matching ""