I end the exploration of order by showing some algebraic properties of order. The first few results deal with the fact that addition and multiplication preserve order:

Theorem APCO

Addition Preserves Canonical Order: For any x,y,zNx,y,z\in\mathbb{N}, xyx \leq y, iff x+zy+zx+z \leq y+z.

Proof: Suppose xyx \leq y. Then one has a kNk\in\mathbb{N} such that x+k=yx+k=y. Hence, (x+k)+z=x+(k+z)=x+(z+k)=(x+z)+k=y+z (x+k)+z=x+(k+z)=x+(z+k)=(x+z)+k=y+z So, x+zy+zx+z \leq y+z.

Conversely, supposing x+zy+zx+z \leq y+z, by the the same sequence of equalities as above (except in reverse), one has that for some natural kk, (x+k)+z=y+z(x+k)+z=y+z. Then, by cancellation, one has that x+k=yx+k=y i.e. xyx \leq y.

However, it is not the case that addition preserves divisibility. For instance, 11 certainly divides 22; but, as shown previously, 1+1=21+1=2 does not divide 2+1=32+1=3.

Corollary APCOStrict

Addition Preserves Strict Order: For any x,y,zNx,y,z\in\mathbb{N}, x<yx<y, iff x+z<y+zx+z<y+z.

Theorem MPO

Multiplication Preserves Order: For any x,y,zNx,y,z\in\mathbb{N}, if xyx \leq y, then zxzyz \cdot x \leq z \cdot y. Also, if z0z \neq 0 and zxzyz \cdot x \leq z \cdot y, then xyx \leq y. Furthermore, if x  yx\ |\ y, then xz  yzx \cdot z\ |\ y \cdot z and, as a partial converse, if xz  yzx \cdot z\ |\ y \cdot z and z0z \neq 0, then x  yx\ |\ y.

Proof: Suppose that xyx \leq y. Then, x+k=yx+k=y for some natural kk. So, z(x+k)=zx+zk=zy z \cdot (x+k)=z \cdot x+z \cdot k=z \cdot y by distributivity. Hence, zxzyz \cdot x \leq z \cdot y.

Now for the reverse direction (along with z0z \neq 0), one needs induction on xx:

  1. If x=0x=0, then obviously xyx \leq y because 00 is the least natural number period.
  2. Now assume that the reverse direction is true for some xx. Now, suppose zS(x)=zx+zzyz \cdot S(x)=z \cdot x+z \leq z \cdot y and z0z \neq 0. Then, for some natural kk, (zx+z)+k=zx+(z+k)=zy (z \cdot x+z)+k=z \cdot x+(z+k)=z \cdot y Thus, zxzyz \cdot x \leq z \cdot y. So, by the inductive hypothesis, xyx \leq y. Now, since z0z \neq 0, it cannot have inverses. Therefore, z+k0z+k \neq 0, so that zxzyz \cdot x \neq z \cdot y by (the contrapositive of) cancellation. Thus, xyx \neq y; otherwise, multiplication being a function, zxz \cdot x would have equaled zyz \cdot y. Hence, x<yx<y. But then, as S(x)S(x) is the least element strictly greater than xx, S(x)yS(x) \leq y, which was to be shown.

The proof of the second part of the theorem, concerning divisibility, is trivial: if xk=yx \cdot k=y, then, certainly, (xz)k=x(zk)=x(kz)=(xk)z=yz (x \cdot z) \cdot k=x \cdot (z \cdot k)=x \cdot (k \cdot z)=(x \cdot k) \cdot z=y \cdot z For the partial converse, simply replicate the algebra above, in a different order, and then multiplicatively cancel out zz (possible as z0z \neq 0).

Corollary MPOStrict

Multiplication Preserves Strict Order: For any x,y,zNx,y,z\in\mathbb{N}, where z0z \neq 0, x<yx<y iff zx<zyz \cdot x<z \cdot y.

 

Of course, in all the theorems and corollaries above, one can change whether zz adds/multiplies from the left or the right by commutativity. Next, I define a limited from of subtraction which uses order to enforce the condition that only smaller (or equal) values should be subtracted from larger (or equal) values:

Definition LimSub

Note first that for x,yNx,y\in\mathbb{N}, if xyx \leq y, then, by definition, one has a kNk\in\mathbb{N} such that x+k=yx+k=y. This kk is, in fact, unique. For if there were another kNk'\in\mathbb{N} such that x+k=yx+k'=y, then one would have x+k=x+kx+k=x+k', so that, by cancellation, k=kk=k'.

Recall next that \leq is actually a subset of N×N\mathbb{N}\times\mathbb{N}. Define, now, the following set  ={(y,x)N×N: (x,y) } \geq\ =\{(y,x)\in\mathbb{N}\times\mathbb{N}:\ (x,y)\in\ \leq\} and then define subtraction as an infix-function :  N-:\ \geq\ \to\mathbb{N} as follows. For any (y,x) (y,x)\in\ \geq, by definition, xyx \leq y, so that there is a unique δxyN\delta_x^y\in\mathbb{N} such that x+δxy=yx+\delta_x^y=y; so, simply set yx=δxyy-x=\delta_x^y.

The reader can proceed to investigate various algebraic properties of this definition. He or she will quickly find out that this subtraction is neither commutative nor even associative! However, multiplication does distribute over it.

 

Next, I define approximate forms of the division function

Definition ApproxDiv

Approximate division comes in two forms: one form is floored while the other form is ceiling-ed. First, for any x,yNx,y\in\mathbb{N} with y0y \neq 0, define Lx/y={pN: ypx}L_{x/y}=\{p\in\mathbb{N}:\ y \cdot p \leq x\} and Ux/y={pN: xyp}U_{x/y}=\{p\in\mathbb{N}:\ x \leq y \cdot p\}. I leave it to the readers to check that both of these sets are always non-empty and that, in the case of Lx/yL_{x/y}, it is bounded above (y0y \neq 0 is crucial for showing this!). Hence, by the two forms of well-ordering, one can respectively define:

  • /:N×(N{0})(x,y)max(Lx/y)N\lfloor\square/\square\rfloor:\mathbb{N}\times(\mathbb{N}\setminus\{0\})\ni(x,y)\mapsto\text{max}(L_{x/y})\in\mathbb{N}
  • /:N×(N{0})(x,y)min(Ux/y)N\lceil\square/\square\rceil:\mathbb{N}\times(\mathbb{N}\setminus\{0\})\ni(x,y)\mapsto\text{min}(U_{x/y})\in\mathbb{N}

The reader can also check the following properties for him or herself:

  • x/yx/y\lfloor x/y \rfloor \leq \lceil x/y \rceil
  • x/y=x/y\lfloor x/y \rfloor = \lceil x/y \rceil iff there exists a pNp\in\mathbb{N} such that yp=xy \cdot p=x. Note that, such a pp must be both max(Lx/y)\text{max}(L_{x/y}) and min(Ux/y)\text{min}(U_{x/y}). Therefore, it has to be unique, as greatest and least elements always are. Hence, in this case, one writes this pp as simply x/yx/y.
  • zx/y(zx)/yz\cdot\lfloor x/y \rfloor \leq \lfloor (z \cdot x)/y \rfloor and (zx)/yzx/y\lceil (z \cdot x)/y \rceil \leq z\cdot\lceil x/y \rceil; but if x/y=x/y\lfloor x/y \rfloor = \lceil x/y \rceil, then z(x/y)=(zx)/yz \cdot (x/y)=(z \cdot x)/y

No doubt, the reader can think of the usual properties of normal division and test how they fare against these limited forms of division.

Definition LimDiv

As with limited subtraction, one can also define limited division. Unlike the two forms of approximate division, this is defined by restricting the domain of division to the following set: op ={(x,y)N×N: (y,x) } |^\textbf{op}\ =\{(x,y)\in\mathbb{N}\times\mathbb{N}:\ (y,x)\in\ |\} Now define the infix /: op N/:\ |^\textbf{op}\ \to\mathbb{N} as follows. Given (x,y) op (x,y)\in\ |^\textbf{op}\ , one has that y  xy\ |\ x. Now, there are two cases:

  • If y=0y=0, then xx has to be 00 also and, thus, one has many choices of naturals kk such that yk=0k=0=xy \cdot k=0 \cdot k=0=x. One can choose any one of these naturals as the definition of x/y=0/0x/y=0/0. For simplicity, I chose 11.
  • If y0y \neq 0, then, there is a unique natural kk such that yk=xy \cdot k=x. So define x/yx/y to be this kk.

results matching ""

    No results matching ""